Science, responsibility, and the philosophical imagination

Publikation: Beitrag in FachzeitschriftArtikelForschungPeer-Review

Autoren

  • Matthew Sample
Forschungs-netzwerk anzeigen

Details

OriginalspracheEnglisch
Aufsatznummer79
FachzeitschriftSYNTHESE
Jahrgang200
Ausgabenummer2
PublikationsstatusVeröffentlicht - 8 März 2022

Abstract

If we cannot define science using only analysis or description, then we must rely on imagination to provide us with suitable objects of philosophical inquiry. This process ties our intellectual findings to the particular ways in which we philosophers think about scientific practice and carve out a cognitive space between real world practice and conceptual abstraction. As an example, I consider Heather Douglas’s work on the responsibilities of scientists and document her implicit ideal of science, defined primarily as an epistemic practice. I then contrast her idealization of science with an alternative: “technoscience,” a heuristic concept used to describe nanotechnology, synthetic biology, and similar “Mode 2” forms of research. This comparison reveals that one’s preferred imaginary of science, even when inspired by real practices, has significant implications for the distribution of responsibility. Douglas’s account attributes moral obligations to scientists, while the imaginaries associated with “technoscience” and “Mode 2 science” spread responsibility across the network of practice. This dynamic between mind and social order, I argue, demands an ethics of imagination in which philosophers of science hold themselves accountable for their imaginaries. Extending analogous challenges from feminist philosophy and Mills’s. “Ideal Theory’ as Ideology,” I conclude that we ought to reflect on the idiosyncrasy of the philosophical imagination and consider how our idealizations of science, if widely held, would affect our communities and broader society.

ASJC Scopus Sachgebiete

Zitieren

Science, responsibility, and the philosophical imagination. / Sample, Matthew.
in: SYNTHESE, Jahrgang 200, Nr. 2, 79, 08.03.2022.

Publikation: Beitrag in FachzeitschriftArtikelForschungPeer-Review

Sample M. Science, responsibility, and the philosophical imagination. SYNTHESE. 2022 Mär 8;200(2):79. doi: 10.1007/s11229-022-03612-2
Sample, Matthew. / Science, responsibility, and the philosophical imagination. in: SYNTHESE. 2022 ; Jahrgang 200, Nr. 2.
Download
@article{3f178e08b45e4b94a1747adb8015ef6b,
title = "Science, responsibility, and the philosophical imagination",
abstract = "If we cannot define science using only analysis or description, then we must rely on imagination to provide us with suitable objects of philosophical inquiry. This process ties our intellectual findings to the particular ways in which we philosophers think about scientific practice and carve out a cognitive space between real world practice and conceptual abstraction. As an example, I consider Heather Douglas{\textquoteright}s work on the responsibilities of scientists and document her implicit ideal of science, defined primarily as an epistemic practice. I then contrast her idealization of science with an alternative: “technoscience,” a heuristic concept used to describe nanotechnology, synthetic biology, and similar “Mode 2” forms of research. This comparison reveals that one{\textquoteright}s preferred imaginary of science, even when inspired by real practices, has significant implications for the distribution of responsibility. Douglas{\textquoteright}s account attributes moral obligations to scientists, while the imaginaries associated with “technoscience” and “Mode 2 science” spread responsibility across the network of practice. This dynamic between mind and social order, I argue, demands an ethics of imagination in which philosophers of science hold themselves accountable for their imaginaries. Extending analogous challenges from feminist philosophy and Mills{\textquoteright}s. “Ideal Theory{\textquoteright} as Ideology,” I conclude that we ought to reflect on the idiosyncrasy of the philosophical imagination and consider how our idealizations of science, if widely held, would affect our communities and broader society.",
keywords = "Imaginaries, Institutions, Philosophy of science, Society, Values and responsibility",
author = "Matthew Sample",
year = "2022",
month = mar,
day = "8",
doi = "10.1007/s11229-022-03612-2",
language = "English",
volume = "200",
journal = "SYNTHESE",
issn = "1573-0964",
publisher = "Springer Netherlands",
number = "2",

}

Download

TY - JOUR

T1 - Science, responsibility, and the philosophical imagination

AU - Sample, Matthew

PY - 2022/3/8

Y1 - 2022/3/8

N2 - If we cannot define science using only analysis or description, then we must rely on imagination to provide us with suitable objects of philosophical inquiry. This process ties our intellectual findings to the particular ways in which we philosophers think about scientific practice and carve out a cognitive space between real world practice and conceptual abstraction. As an example, I consider Heather Douglas’s work on the responsibilities of scientists and document her implicit ideal of science, defined primarily as an epistemic practice. I then contrast her idealization of science with an alternative: “technoscience,” a heuristic concept used to describe nanotechnology, synthetic biology, and similar “Mode 2” forms of research. This comparison reveals that one’s preferred imaginary of science, even when inspired by real practices, has significant implications for the distribution of responsibility. Douglas’s account attributes moral obligations to scientists, while the imaginaries associated with “technoscience” and “Mode 2 science” spread responsibility across the network of practice. This dynamic between mind and social order, I argue, demands an ethics of imagination in which philosophers of science hold themselves accountable for their imaginaries. Extending analogous challenges from feminist philosophy and Mills’s. “Ideal Theory’ as Ideology,” I conclude that we ought to reflect on the idiosyncrasy of the philosophical imagination and consider how our idealizations of science, if widely held, would affect our communities and broader society.

AB - If we cannot define science using only analysis or description, then we must rely on imagination to provide us with suitable objects of philosophical inquiry. This process ties our intellectual findings to the particular ways in which we philosophers think about scientific practice and carve out a cognitive space between real world practice and conceptual abstraction. As an example, I consider Heather Douglas’s work on the responsibilities of scientists and document her implicit ideal of science, defined primarily as an epistemic practice. I then contrast her idealization of science with an alternative: “technoscience,” a heuristic concept used to describe nanotechnology, synthetic biology, and similar “Mode 2” forms of research. This comparison reveals that one’s preferred imaginary of science, even when inspired by real practices, has significant implications for the distribution of responsibility. Douglas’s account attributes moral obligations to scientists, while the imaginaries associated with “technoscience” and “Mode 2 science” spread responsibility across the network of practice. This dynamic between mind and social order, I argue, demands an ethics of imagination in which philosophers of science hold themselves accountable for their imaginaries. Extending analogous challenges from feminist philosophy and Mills’s. “Ideal Theory’ as Ideology,” I conclude that we ought to reflect on the idiosyncrasy of the philosophical imagination and consider how our idealizations of science, if widely held, would affect our communities and broader society.

KW - Imaginaries

KW - Institutions

KW - Philosophy of science

KW - Society

KW - Values and responsibility

UR - http://www.scopus.com/inward/record.url?scp=85126232096&partnerID=8YFLogxK

U2 - 10.1007/s11229-022-03612-2

DO - 10.1007/s11229-022-03612-2

M3 - Article

VL - 200

JO - SYNTHESE

JF - SYNTHESE

SN - 1573-0964

IS - 2

M1 - 79

ER -